Consumerism critic Baudrillard dies

Jean Baudrillard, the French sociologist and philosopher and critic of globalisation and consumerism, has died in Paris at the age of 77.

Baudrillard died on Tuesday at his home in Paris after a long illness, said Michel Delorme, of the Galilee publishing house.

Baudrillard was a prolific writer and renowned photographer who first attracted worldwide attention in 1991 with the deliberately provocative claim that the Gulf War “did not take place”.

He was one of Europe’s leading postmodernist thinkers known for his provocative commentaries on consumerism.

Critic of modern society

Baudrillard argued that neither side could claim victory by the end of the war and that the conflict had changed nothing on the ground in ?>Iraq.?>

Just over a decade on, in an essay entitled The Spirit of Terrorism: Requiem for the Twin Towers, he courted fresh controversy by describing the September 11, 2001 attacks in the United States as an expression of “triumphant globalisation battling against itself”.

  

Born in Rheims on July 29, 1929, into a peasant family, he studied German at the Sorbonne, later working as a teacher and translator of Bertolt Brecht before his interests turned to sociology.

  

Baudrillard taught sociology throughout the 1960s and went on to develop a stinging – some say nihilistic – critique of modern society.

  

He was the author of more than 50 works including: The Mirror of Production (1973), Simulacra and Simulation (1981), America (1986), and The Spirit of Terrorism: A Requiem for the Twin Towers (2002).
—————
Introduction to work

Jean Baudrillard was a social theorist best known for his analyses of modes of mediation and technological communication, although the scope of his writing spreads across more diverse subjects — from consumerism, to gender relations, to the social understanding of history through to more journalistic commentaries on AIDS, cloning, the Rushdie affair, the (first) Gulf War and the attacks on the World Trade Center. He had affinities with post-structuralism in that his arguments consistently drew on the notion that systems of signification and meaning are only understandable in terms of their interrelation. In contrast to Foucault however, of whom he was sharply critical, Baudrillard developed theories based, not on power and knowledge, but around the notions of seduction, simulation, and, the term with which he is most associated, hyperreality. These notions all share the common principle that signification, and therefore meaning, is self-referential (construed, following structuralist semiotics, in terms of absence — so ‘dog’ means ‘dog’ not because of what the word says but because it does not say: ‘cat’, ‘goat’, ‘tree’ etc.). Baudrillard uses this principle to argue that in our present ‘global’ society, wherein technological communication has created an excessive proliferation of meaning, meaning’s self-referentiality has prompted, not a McLuhan-style ‘global village’, but a world where meaning has been effaced and society has been reduced to an opaque mass, where the ‘real’ has been reduced to the self-referential signs of its existence.

Given his postulate, of the erosion of meaning via its excess, Baudrillard — against Foucault, but also against Kantian rationalism and liberal humanism — has sought to understand the world neither in terms of the subject’s desire to coherently know the world nor in terms of the interpolation of power within subjectivity (in the manner of Foucault), but in terms of the object and its power to seduce (its power to stand for, or to simulate). As a result Baudrillard had, particularly in his later work, ‘withdrawn’ himself, in a sense, from his own writing, by way of employing a poetic and ironic dynamic in his books. In terms of Baudrillard’s political standpoint, such an effort has led him — drawing on the anthropological work of Marcel Mauss and Georges Bataille — to increasingly oppose semiotic logic, that of meaning, sign, signification, and commodity exchange, with that of the symbolic realm: that of gift exchange, potlatch (the practice of sumptuous destruction), and analyses of the principle of Evil (and what it means to invoke the principle of Evil). This had prompted him to characterize the world in terms of a binary opposition of symbolic cultures (based upon gift exchange) and the ever-expanding ‘globalized’ world, based on sign and commodity exchange, a world which has no answer to symbolic logic. Hence Baudrillard was, portentously, in his final years of the opinion that the expansion of liberal parliamentary capitalism, and the increasing reach of financial commodification that goes with it, unwittingly sows the seeds of that which reacts against it by its failure to understand the symbolic side to social existence — indeed, controversially, he argued that that is how best to understand the events of September 11th (see below).

[edit]
The object value system

Baudrillard’s early work, in the books The System of Objects, For a Critique of the Political Economy of the Sign and The Consumer Society, focused on the application of structural semiotics to the thought of Karl Marx. Baudrillard argued, drawing from Roland Barthes and Georges Bataille, that while Marxist economics and the classical economics of Adam Smith had sought to understand the consumer society in opposing ways, both accepted the nature of use value without question. They both therefore misunderstood need in the same way: always as a genuine, asocially constituted drive for a given consumer’s satisfaction. Against this Baudrillard argued that an individual necessarily, in purchasing and consuming goods, places him or herself within a system of signs; objects therefore always ‘say something’ about their users. He thus developed a theory of society governed by a system of sumptuous, sacrificial consumption, in which needs become ‘ideologically generated'[3]. Baudrillard described this system in terms of four processes of obtaining value:
A functional value of an object, its instrumental purpose. (A pen writes; a fridge cools etc.) This is what Marx referred to as the ‘use-value’ of the commodity.
An exchange value of an object, its economic value. (A pen is worth three pencils; a fridge is worth three months’ salary.)
A symbolic value of an object, its arbitrarily assigned and agreed value in relation to another subject. (A pen represents a graduation present or a speaker’s gift; a diamond ring symbolizes a public declaration of love between two individuals.)
A sign value of an object, its value in a system of objects. (A pen is part of a desk set, or a particular pen confers social status; a diamond ring has sign value in relation to other diamond rings, or the absence of a ring. The human subject is interpolated, perhaps eroded, in the ‘seductive’ play of objects.)

Baudrillard later went on to eventually reject Marxism outright (in The Mirror of Production and Symbolic Exchange and Death) but the opposition of the semiotic functional logic and the logic of the symbolic realm continued in his later work until death.

[edit]
Simulacra and simulation

The development of Baudrillard’s work throughout the 1980s saw him move away from economically-based theories to considerations of mediation and mass communication. Although he retained an interest in Saussurean semiotics and the logic of symbolic exchange (under the influence of the anthropologist Marcel Mauss) Baudrillard increasingly turned his attention to the likes of Marshall McLuhan, developing ideas about how the nature of social relations is determined by the forms of communication that a society employs. In doing so Baudrillard actually moved beyond both Saussure’s and Roland Barthes’ formal semiology to consider the implications of a historically understood, and thus formless, version of structural semiology.

Most famously he argued — in the book Symbolic Exchange and Death — that Western societies have undergone a “precession of simulacra”.[4] This precession, according to Baudrillard, took the form of “orders of simulacra” from
the era of the original
to the counterfeit
to the produced, mechanical copy, and through
to the simulated “third order of simulacra” whereby the copy has come to replace the original.

Referring to “On Exactitude in Science”, a fable by Borges and Adolfo Bioy Casares, Baudrillard argued that for present day society as the simulated copy had superseded the original so the map had come to precede the territory (see map/territory relation). So it was, for example, with the first Gulf War (see below): the image of war came to precede genuine conflict.

Using this line of reasoning, Baudrillard came to characterise the present age — following on from Ludwig Feuerbach and Guy Debord — as one of ‘hyperreality’ where the real has come to be effaced or superseded by the signs of its existence. Such an assertion — the one for which Baudrillard has drawn most and his heaviest criticism — is typical of Baudrillard’s “fatal strategy” of attempting to push his theories of society beyond themselves, so to speak. Rather than saying, for instance, that our hysteria surrounding pedophilia is such that we no longer really understand what childhood is anymore, Baudrillard argued that “the Child no longer exists”.[5] Similarly, rather than arguing — in a similar manner to Susan Sontag in her book On Photography — that the notion of reality has been complicated by the profusion of images of it, Baudrillard came to assert: “the real no longer exists”. In so doing Baudrillard came to characterise his philosophical challenge as being no longer the Leibnizian question of: “Why is there something rather than nothing?”, but rather: “Why is there nothing rather than something?”[6]

[edit]
The end of history and meaning

Baudrillard’s most in-depth writings on the notion of historicity are found in the books Fatal Strategies and The Illusion of the End. It is for these writings that he received a full-chapter denunciation from the physicist Alan Sokal (along with Jean Bricmont), due to his alleged misuse of physical concepts of linear time, space and stability. His argument can be summarised as being an attempted subversion of the thesis of Francis Fukuyama that the collapse of Soviet Communism brought humanity to the ‘end of History’ whereby the world’s global dialectical machinations had been resolved with the triumph of liberal capitalism. In contrast to this, Baudrillard maintained that the ‘end of History’, in terms of a teleogical goal, had always been an illusion brought about by modernity’s will towards progress, civilization and rational unification. And this was an illusion that to all intents and purposes vanished toward the end of the 20th century, brought about by the ‘speed’ at which society moved, effectively ‘destabilising’ the linear progression of History (it is these comments, specifically, that provoked Sokal’s criticism). History was, so to speak, outpaced by its own spectacular realisation. As Baudrillard himself caustically put it:
The end of history is, alas, also the end of the dustbins of history. There are no longer any dustbins for disposing of old ideologies, old regimes, old values. Where are we going to throw Marxism, which actually invented the dustbins of history? (Yet there is some justice here since the very people who invented them have fallen in.) Conclusion: if there are no more dustbins of history, this is because History itself has become a dustbin. It has become its own dustbin, just as the planet itself is becoming its own dustbin.[7]

This approach to history is what marks out Baudrillard’s affinities with the postmodern philosophy of Jean-Francois Lyotard: the idea that society — and Western society in particular — has ‘dropped out’ of the grand narratives of History (for example the coming of Communism or the triumph of civilized modern society). But Baudrillard supplemented this argument by contending that, although this ‘dropping out’ may have taken place, the global world (which in Baudrillard’s writing is sharply distinct from a universal humanity) is, in accordance with its spectacular understanding of itself, condemned to ‘play out’ this illusory ending in a hyper-teleological way — acting out the end of the end of the end, ad infinitum. Thus Baudrillard argues that — in a manner similar to Giorgio Agamben’s book Means without Ends — Western society is subject to the political restriction of means that are justified by ends that do not exist.

[edit]
On the Gulf War

Much of Baudrillard’s notoriety as an academic and political commentator comes from his deliberately provocative claim in 1991 that the first Gulf War ‘did not take place.’ His argument — which sparked heavy criticism from the likes of Chris Norris (see below) who perceived, in Baudrillard, a denial of empirical events — described the war as the inverse of the Clausewitzian formula: not ‘the continuation of politics by other means’, but ‘the continuation of the absence of politics by other means.’ According to Baudrillard, Saddam Hussein was not fighting the Allied Forces, but using the lives of his troops as a form of sacrifice to preserve his power (p. 72 in the 2004 edition); and neither were the Allied Forces fighting Saddam, they were merely dropping 10,000 tonnes of bombs a day as if to prove to themselves there was an enemy to fight (p. 61). So too were the Western media complicit, presenting the war in ‘real time’ and recycling images of war to propagate the notion that the two enemies were in actual conflict. But, Baudrillard followed, this was not the case: Saddam did not use what military capacity he had (his air force); nor was his power eventually weakened (as he managed to put down the insurgency against him after the war ended). And so, Baudrillard concluded, little politically changed in Iraq: the enemy was not defeated, the victors were not victorious. Ergo, there was no war: the Gulf War did not take place.

Much of the repute that Baudrillard found as a result of the book (which previously was printed in article form in the British newspaper The Guardian and the French paper Libération) was based upon the criticism that the war was not as ineffectual as Baudrillard portrayed it: people died, the political map was altered, and Saddam’s regime was harmed. Some criticisms (Norris included) go so far as to accuse Baudrillard of a form of ‘instant revisionism’; a denial of the physical occurrence of the conflict (part of his denial of reality in general). He has in consequence been at the receiving end of accusations of lazy amoralism, all-encompassing cynical scepticism or Berkelian idealism. More sympathetic commentators (such as William Merrin, in his book Baudrillard and the Media) have argued however that Baudrillard was more concerned with the techno-political dominance of the West, and globalization, and what it means for the present possibility of war. Merrin, for instance, has averred that Baudrillard did not deny that something took place, but merely denied that that something was a war; rather it was ‘an atrocity masquerading as a war’. Merrin’s book in fact viewed the accusations of amorality as redundant and based upon misreading; Baudrillard’s own position, it held, was in fact more nuanced. To put it in Baudrillard’s own words (p. 71-72):
Saddam liquidates the communists, Moscow flirts even more with him; he gases the Kurds, it is not held against him; he eliminates the religious cadres, the whole of Islam makes peace with him…. Even … the 100,000 dead will only have been the final decoy that Saddam will have sacrificed, the blood money paid in forfeit according to a calculated equivalence, in order to conserve his power. What is worse is that these dead still serve as an alibi for those who do not want to have been excited for nothing: at least these dead will prove this war was indeed a war and not a shameful and pointless hoax….

[edit]
On the 9/11 attacks

In contrast to the ‘non-event’ of the Gulf War, Baudrillard, in his essay The Spirit of Terrorism characterised the attacks on the World Trade Center as the ‘absolute event.’ He sought to understand them in terms of an (ab)reaction to the techno-political expansion of globalization, rather than in terms of a religious or civilization-based conflict. He termed the event and its consequences as follows (p. 11 in the 2002 version):
This is not a clash of civilisations or religions, and it reaches far beyond Islam and America, on which efforts are being made to focus the conflict in order to create the delusion of a visible confrontation and a solution based upon force. There is indeed a fundamental antagonism here, but one that points past the spectre of America (which is perhaps the epicentre, but in no sense the sole embodiment, of globalisation) and the spectre of Islam (which is not the embodiment of terrorism either) to triumphant globalisation battling against itself.

Baudrillard thus placed the attacks — in a manner befitting his theoretical approach to society — firmly in the context of a symbolic reaction to the continued expansion of a world based solely upon commodity exchange. This approach has led him to be criticised on two counts. Firstly, Richard Wolin (in the book The Seduction of Unreason) forcefully accused Baudrillard, along with Slavoj Zizek, of all but celebrating the attacks, and in essence claiming the U.S. got what it deserved. Zizek, however, has countered this accusation, referring (in the journal Critical Inquiry) to Wolin’s analysis as a form of ‘intellectual barbarism,’ flatly stating that Wolin fails to see the difference between fantasising about an event, and deserving that event. Merrin (again in Baudrillard and the Media) nonetheless has argued that such a position as Baudrillard’s does afford the terrorists a certain position — indeed Merrin (in the journal Economy and Society) has pointed to the weakness of Baudrillard’s argument being that he gives the symbolic facets of society unfair privilege over and above semiotic concerns. This leads to the second criticism of Baudrillard’s position on 9/11 (made by Bruno Latour, again in Critical Inquiry): that Baudrillard’s 9/11 was ineluctable. Because Baudrillard only conceived of society in terms of a symbolic/semiotic dualism, he alluded to the towers being, as it were, ‘brought down by their own weight’ — forced into destruction by the society that created them.

[edit]
Critiques of Baudrillard

Baudrillard’s writing, and his uncompromising positions, led to criticism the force of which can only be compared to, in contemporary social scholarship, Jacques Lacan. Only one of the two major confrontational book-length critiques — Christopher Norris’s Uncritical Theory: Postmodernism, Intellectuals and the Gulf War (ISBN 0-87023-817-5) — however seeks to reject his media theory and position on ‘the real’ out of hand. The other — Douglas Kellner’s Jean Baudrillard: From Marxism to Postmodernism and Beyond (ISBN 0-8047-1757-5) — seeks rather to analyse Baudrillard’s relation to postmodernism (a concept with which Baudrillard has had a continued, if uneasy and rarely explicit relationship) and to present a Marxist counter. Regarding the former, William Merrin (as discussed above) has published more than one denunciation of Norris’s position. The latter Baudrillard himself characterised as reductive (in Nicholas Zurbrugg’s Jean Baudrillard: Art and Artefact).

Willam Merrin’s work has presented a more sympathetic critique, which attempts to ‘place Baudrillard in opposition to himself.’ Thereby Merrin has argued that Baudrillard’s position on semiotic analysis of meaning denies himself his own position on symbolic exchange. Merrin thus alludes to the common criticism of post-structuralist work (a criticism not dissimilar in either Baudrillard, Foucault or Deleuze) that emphasising interrelation as the basis for subjectivity denies the human agency from which social structures necessarily arise. (Alain Badiou and Michel de Certeau have made this point generally, and Barry Sandywell has argued as much in Baudrillard’s specific case).

Finally Mark Poster, Baudrillard’s main editor and one of a number of present day academics who argue for his contemporary relevance, has remarked (p. 8 of Poster’s 2nd ed. of Selected Writings):
Baudrillard’s writing up to the mid-1980s is open to several criticisms. He fails to define key terms, such as the code; his writing style is hyperbolic and declarative, often lacking sustained, systematic analysis when it is appropriate; he totalizes his insights, refusing to qualify or delimit his claims. He writes about particular experiences, television images, as if nothing else in society mattered, extrapolating a bleak view of the world from that limited base. He ignores contradictory evidence such as the many benefits afforded by the new media….

Nonetheless Poster is keen to refute the most extreme of Baudrillard’s critics, the likes of Alan Sokal and Norris who see him as a purveyor of a form of reality-denying irrationalism (ibid p. 7):
Baudrillard is not disputing the trivial issue that reason remains operative in some actions, that if I want to arrive at the next block, for example, I can assume a Newtonian universe (common sense), plan a course of action (to walk straight for X meters, carry out the action, and finally fulfil my goal by arriving at the point in question). What is in doubt is that this sort of thinking enables a historically informed grasp of the present in general. According to Baudrillard, it does not. The concurrent spread of the hyperreal through the media and the collapse of liberal and Marxist politics as the master narratives, deprives the rational subject of its privileged access to truth. In an important sense individuals are no longer citizens, eager to maximise their civil rights, nor proletarians, anticipating the onset of communism. They are rather consumers, and hence the prey of objects as defined by the code.

Denhoff, Grisey, Neuwirth

Denhoff, Grisey, Neuwirth

[April 2006.]

Cover of confido 270405

Michael DENHOFF: Sounds and Shadows — Klavierwerke
von Michael Denhoff
. Susanne Kessel (piano), Selçuk
Sahinoglu (clar.). confido 270405. No American distributor,
but available directly from confido/Capitol Sound Studios (info@capitolsound.de).

German pianist Susanne Kessel is one of European new music’s
greatest friends and this new release is another demonstration of her
ability to perform with charm, grace and virtuosity. Michael Denhoff
(b. 1955), a resident of Bonn, occupies a unique position in German music.
His influences come not so much from Lachenmann or Stockhausen as from
Feldman, Kurtág and Nono, with touches of the post-expressionism
of his German predecessors Boris Blacher or Bernd Alois Zimmermann. The
core duality of his music lies almost always between light and shadow,
introvert and extrovert, rendering each piece familiar yet unpredictable.

The opening work, … al niente …,
Op. 95 (2002), builds from a Feldmanesque motif which appears and disappears
regularly, in whole or in part, later in alternation with a more restive
theme. In its 23 minutes, it presents a vast spectrum of piano polarities,
from the instrument’s high haze to its lowest growl, each shift
in temperament separated by shoals of silence. Next is the nine-movement
set of miniatures called Nachtschattengewächse, Op.
96 (2001/04). Each subtitled movement centers on themes of night, growth,
mystery and light. This does not imply that the piece offers a unified
front. Indeed, its nine movements, ranging from 0:24 to 2:44, hold more
surprises than reprises. The last work is the most introspective and
the CD’s namesake, Sounds and Shadows, Op. 86b (1999).
Its 33 minutes are mostly subdued, its inward glances seeming more personal
and elusive than those of the opening piece. In the work’s second
half, almost imperceptibly, a distant, on-and-off-again clarinet reflects
on Kessel’s monologue. The closing passages are relegated solely
to the clarinet, an autumnal foghorn from afar. The music’s duration
bespeaks an intense level of engagement, the now plaintive, now anxious
textures aptly summing Denhoff’s aesthetic. Thanks in good part
to an excellent recording, Kessel sparkles throughout these rich soundscapes.

Cover of Kairos 0012422KAI

Gérard GRISEY: Les Espaces Acoustiques.
Andrew Joy, Joachim Pöltl, Kathleen Putnam, Hubert Stähle (horns),
Garth Knox (viola), Stephan Blaumer (viola), Stefan Asbury (cond.), Asko
Ensemble, WDR Sinfonieorchester Köln. Kairos 0012422KAI (http://www.kairos-music.com/).
Distributed in the US by ArkivMusic (http://www.arkivmusic.com/).

Had he lived, Gérard Grisey would be 60 this year.
Along with the late ensemble work Vortex Temporum, Les
Espaces Acoustiques
stands as his crowning achievement. The cycle,
one of the most ambitious of its time, spans 1974-85, and this is its
second complete recording. It could not be more different from its predecessor
on Accord, with Pierre-André Valade and Court-circuit in
the ensemble works, and the Frankfurter Museumsorchester in the cycle’s
second half under Sylvain Cambreling’s direction. (See timetable
below for a breakdown of the most noticeable discrepancy: duration.)

Les Espaces Acoustiques accrues in instrumentation
from a solo viola to a septet to 18 players to 33 players to 83 players
to four solo horns and 82 players. Listening to these competing cycles
back-to-back is a rather startling experience. Tempi fluctuate wildly.
Here, the Dutch and German performers require 97 minutes for the six-piece
set, whereas the French take 87. Court-circuit, devoted to the spectral
school, delivers the more authoritative account, largely because the
music benefits from a quicker, but by no means harried, pace. I prefer
by a slight margin Garth Knox’s account of the Prologue to
the one on Accord, not because it is speedier, but because he
brings a greater tension to the music’s lyricism alternating with
brusque force. The Asko performance also proves enlightening, as in the
more sensual effects of the middle sections, Périodes (7
players), Partiels (18 players) and Modulations (33
players), the interpretation more obviously lingering on the score’s
pure auditory beauty. This slow-footed Périodes,
alas, falls short of the piercing quality of its companion section. The
climactic passages require a motoric drive lacking here. Despite excellent
musicianship, Asko’s Partiels seems equally stupefied
and directionless. Both readings of the rhythmically complex Transitoires show
this to be an orchestral masterpiece of shifting contours. Both surpass
Pierre Boulez’s original recording of Modulations (Erato
4509-98496-2
, O/P), a work which he seems not to have understood.
Asbury again delineates the textures somewhat in Modulations and Transitoires,
but to no great detriment.

The playing in both cases warrants praise. The sets complement
each other in gratifying ways. Because of the sheer cohesion his musicians
bring to the scores, Valade leaves a greater impression and will probably
be the standard against which future recordings are judged. However,
in offering committed performances and a radical interpretation, Asbury
succeeds on his own terms.

 

Boulez

Asbury

Valade

Prologue

 

15:28

17:25

Périodes  

15:28

12:49

Partiels  

22:02

18:31

Modulations

18:36

16:10

13:23

Transitoires  

19:54

17:29

Epilogue

 

8:03

7:32

Cover of Kairos 0012462KAI

Olga NEUWIRTH: Chamber music. Akroata
Hadal
(string quartet, 1995); Quasare/Pulsare (violin
/ piano, 1995-96); …?risonanze!… (viola
d’amore, 1996-97); …ad auras…in memoriam
H.
(2 violins / getabera [wooden drum], 1999); incidendo/fluido (piano
and CD-player, 2000); settori (string quartet, 1999).
Irvine Arditti, Graeme Jennings (violins), Garth Knox (viola d’amore),
Nicolas Hodges (piano), Rohan de Saram (cello, getabera), Arditti
String Quartet. Kairos 0012462KAI (http://www.kairos-music.com/).
Distributed in the US by ArkivMusic (http://www.arkivmusic.com/).

Austrian composer Olga Neuwirth (b. 1968) has gained a
reputation of late, no doubt boosted by her previous Kairos CDs
and successful opera Lost Highway, based on the David Lynch
film with a libretto by Nobel laureate Elfriede Jelinek. Her music, while
partaking of a (Johann) Straussian lilt, owes more to Lachenmann & Co.
than to Austria’s belle-époque past. Often impressive and
undeniably well-written, her work lacks individuality. Admittedly, originality
in art need not equal genius, but how, I wonder, does one distinguish
her music from the quotidian work of others of her generation?

The string-quartet pieces which open and close this recording
are stereotypically modernistic and tension-besotted, never quite extending
beyond the parameters Ferneyhough and Lachenmann established decades
ago. The high squeaks say it all. Similarly, Quasare/Pulsare fails
to leave an impression, despite some well-placed violin knocks, piano
preparations, use of the e-bow on the piano, and other by-now-familiar
extended techniques. In avoiding the obvious romantic connotations of
the viola d’amore by exploiting mistunings and atypical resonances
in her …?risonanze!…, the composer scores
a coup. I especially enjoyed the graceful writing for the instrument’s
bridge, nicely setting apart the more predictable filigree work. The
violins-and-drum trio …ad auras…in memoriam H. is
hit-and-miss: Its tunings are again of interest and the occasional drum
accompaniment hearkens back to one of George Antheil’s early violin
/ piano sonatas, but there is too much wandering to sustain one’s
interest. Most noticeable is incidendo/fluido: As the live
piano material centers on the instrument’s middle register, the
listener also hears the distinctive sound of the Ondes Martenot, emanating
from a CD player stored deep within the piano itself and clearly echoing
an idea from Luigi Nono’s …sofferte onde serene….
While there is no direct dialogue between the two sources, the Ondes’ ever-present
hum adds an ethereal dimension to what is otherwise a mostly brutalistic
piece.

As always, the Arditti String Quartet, Garth Knox and Nicolas
Hodges shine. If not for their efforts, this disc would be even less
than the half-engaging amalgam it is.

Boulez: A Master Speaks Anew

Boulez: A Master Speaks Anew

[September 2005.]

Cover of DG 00289 477 5327

Pierre BOULEZ: Le marteau sans maître (1953-55); Dérive
1
(1984); Dérive 2 (1988/2002). Hilary
Summers (mezzo-soprano); members of Ensemble InterContemporain, Pierre
Boulez (cond.). Deutsche Grammophon 00289 477 5327.

There may be no post-World War II work for voice and instrumentalists
more famous than Pierre Boulez’s 1950s song cycle Le marteau
sans maître
. The music’s striking mix of alto voice
(here a mezzo-soprano), alto flute, guitar, viola, vibraphone, xylorimba
and percussion, deft interweaving of instrumental and vocal passages
and the simultaneous, seamless unfolding of three separate cycles-within-a-cycle — to
name but a few of its qualities — set it apart. It is also a work
disdained by the less adventurous for its supposed rigor and inflexibility.
The music operates for many listeners as a line of demarcation, no doubt.
Time has withered its novel effects, but the content remains as strong
today as at its inception, 50 years ago. This recording is the first
on a disc to be easily available stateside. Albeit more confined and
moderate in approach — in other words, “safe” — it
compares favorably with three LPs in my collection. Technically, the
performance seems note-perfect and the music remains thrilling; however,
the verve of earlier recordings has been replaced with a sense of familiarity.
Summers and a sextet of EIC’s finest musicians perform almost mechanically,
perhaps because they didn’t need to learn any new techniques. For
earlier performers, this was difficult sailing. Today the music’s
challenges are commonplace, its direction clearly defined from the outset. Le
marteau sans maître
is not at all an open-form work, and
yet earlier musicians brought more creativity to these same firmly fixed
notes. I’m not complaining, exactly — quibbling, rather.
Precision is never to be discounted.

Dérive 1 and 2 are vastly
different creations. Dérive 1, marked Très
lent, immuable
, a mere six minutes long, features a stately prologue
and epilogue, and an explosive middle replete with undulations from the
six instrumentalists involved: flute, clarinet, violin, cello, piano
and vibraphone. The music has been subtly revised since it was last recorded
on Erato, but the overall experience is unchanged, and the charming
Paul Sacher motif (the notes E-flat, A, C, B, E, D) remains its principal
joy. Dérive 1 is a pristine, undervalued jewel,
easy to overlook. By contrast, Dérive 2 (a first
recording), marked Très rapide, is nearly 25 minutes in
length. The work is scored for English horn, clarinet, bassoon, French
horn, violin, viola, cello, harp, piano, vibraphone and marimba. The
drive of the earlier work’s middle section has been transformed
into a nigh-raucous moto perpetuo, like nothing else in
Boulez’s catalogue. As always, the composer amazes with his control
of timbre and the range of variation his limited instrumentation achieves.
The sublime interplay amongst ever-shifting factions of the ensemble
identifies Boulez’s continually refreshing craft, as compelling
today as ever.

It should come as no surprise that the musicians of EIC
play with an enthusiasm second to none. Even in the somewhat mechanical Marteau,
these virtuosi are never less than convincing.